Partially Resolving the Tension Between

Omniscience and Free Will:  
A Mathematical Argument

Joseph S. Fulda  

      Joseph Fulda is a freelance writer living in New York City. He is the author of Eight Steps Towards Libertarianism.

      One of the thorniest and most intriguing problems in the philosophy of religion has been the tension between man’s free will and God’s omniscience—or more exactly, His foreknowledge. For if He knows in advance what we will do, in what sense can our doing it be free? A standard answer, dating to at least Maimonides, is that the phrase “in advance” is misused. What God knows, He knows timelessly: time is a measure of change in the material and the corporeal; God is outside the realm of the material and the corporeal: His knowledge is therefore qualitatively different from ours and exists, as it were, above and without time. This answer seems to work around the problem rather than addressing it squarely.

      In this article, we sketch a partial resolution to this classical problem by concentrating not so much on God’s omniscience as on His omnipotence. Of course, His omnipotence poses no direct problem for free will, since it is understood that any agents that He has decided to make autonomous will, up to the limits of their autonomy, be free actors. But while God does not control the autonomy of free-willed agents, He certainly does control the environment within which they act; in fact, He controls it omni potently, that is, completely.

      In an article in Mind, “The Mathematical Pull of Temptation,” I put forth a theory of temptation that can be used to show how God’s omnipotence matters, how it can be used to rescue His omniscience in the fact of free-willed agents. Let us briefly review this theory.

      It is assumed by preachers and laymen alike that our steadfastness when presented with an object of temptation depends on (a) our character, and (b) the tempting strength of the object. To paraphrase Henry Ward Beecher on character and temptation: Temptations without imply desires within. A man ought not to say “How powerfully the devil tempts,” but “How strongly I am tempted.” As for the pull of the object, it is the conventional view that the stronger it is, the more likely we are to succumb and the less likely we are to resist.

      We put forward an alternative account of temptation that suggests that both character and the object of temptation may not, in some cases, be considerations, let alone the dominant considerations, in explaining behavior in the face of temptation.

      We arranged a simple thought experiment, which we referred to as “the red case.” A man is placed in a solitary room with a red button and nothing else. For twenty-four hours, he remains alone in that room. Pressing the red button at any time initiates a sequence of sinful events that will culminate in his obtaining the object of his temptation. However slight the pull of the temptation behind the red button, it is a man of very rare will who will be able to resist its continuous lure. The man, that is, is as weak as weakest moment.

      We also arranged the converse thought experiment, which we referred to as “the black case.” A man has already initiated a sequence of events that will result in his obtaining the object of his temptation. Now, he is placed in a solitary room with a black button and nothing else. For twenty-four hours, he remains alone in that room. Pressing the black button just once disrupts the sequence of events that would otherwise produce for him the object of his temptation, and the temptation will have been successfully resisted. However strong the pull of the tempting object, the pull of conscience nearly guarantees that the man will leave his confinement having pressed the black button. The man, that is, is as strong as his strongest moment.

      We continued by presenting the mathematics behind these intuitions. Even if the man in the red case is a very good man, one who normally resists temptation, and even if we can quantify this judgment by saying that a priori, and without our intervention and the lure of the red button, he would succumb to a single presentation of the tempting object only one time in one hundred (and this number does depend on the object), simple probability calculations show that for the 4800 presentations in the red case he is virtually certain (1 - .994800) to succumb. Likewise, even if the man in the black case is very easily swayed by the slightest of desires, and even if we can quantify this judgment by saying that a priori, and without our intervention and the pull of the black button, he would succumb to a single presentation of the tempting object fully ninety-nine times in one hundred (and, again, this number does depend on the object), simple probability calculations show that for the 4800 chances he will have to resist a single presentation he is virtually certain (l - .994800) to resist it. Notice that in either case switching .99 and .01 would make no perceptible difference for any significant number of opportunities to succumb or resist.

      Now, God’s omnipotence places Him in control of the opportunity structure of the world with which we are all daily faced, while man’s autonomous will places him (primarily) in control of the likelihood of his succumbing or resisting an opportunity (what we call character), so the man-God interaction comes down to ab, with man in control of a and God in control of b, and as everyone knows, b dominates a. That is the crux of the (partial) resolution of the tension between omniscience and free will: God sets up the opportunity structure within which we sin or do good and He can force an outcome out of even truly free actors, and even when He does not force an outcome, it may be plain to Him as a simple result of His knowledge of both a and b and his complete control over b. Since we would not expect forcing or prior-knowledge-without-forcing for each of man’s actions, our solution remains partial, but it does suggest an avenue of thought and research on this millennia-old problem.     

      We would like to thank the following people for their generous contributions (made up to July 15, 2003) to the publication of this journal: George E. Andrews, Lee R. Ashmun, Frank J. Bartz, Alexis Bayard, Charles Benscheidt, James L. Bililie, Robert P. Bringer, Georgia Buchta, William L. Burns, Frances G. Campbell, Irma I. Clark, Eugene H. Donovan, Nicholas Falco, Edwin J. Feulner, Richard G. Frost, James R. Gaines, Gary Gillespie, William R. Grant, Dick Herreid, Jaren E. Hiller, Thomas E. Humphreys, David Ihle, Donald C. Ingram, O. Walter Johnson, Robert R. Johnson, Frank G. Kenski, A. R. Kircher, Gloria Knoblauch, Donald Krier, James F. Lammers, Benjamin H. Lane, Donald G. Lee, Calvin T. Lucy, Thomas D. MacStocker, Daniel Maher, Thomas J. McGreevy, David P. and Barbara R. Mitchel, Leonore E. Moberg, Dwight D. Murphey, Harry Neuwirth, Marsha Nickels, William J. Nolan, Frances S. Richardson, Mark and Beth Richter, Howard J. Romanek, Millard H. Ruether, H. Richard Schumacher, Al Shane, Michael Stiennon, Clifford W. Stone, Dennis J. Sullivan, Mary H. Sunberg, Michael S. Swisher, Doug Tice, Jack E. Turner, Johanna Visser, Rodney G. Weiler, Robert D. Wells, George M. Wheatley, James W. Williams.

 

[ Who We Are | Authors | Archive | Subscribtion | Search | Contact Us ]
© Copyright St.Croix Review 2002